Boston, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
Reflection on Just War Theory
The moral justification of war is a deeply contested issue, one side of it developed in the mindset of intrinsicism, the other being deeply rooted in consequentialism. These two ideas fall on opposite sides of the spectrum, each representing incredibly valid ideologies and reasoning. These two perspectives catalyze how society views conflict, justice, and morality collectively. Just War Theory serves as a medium to which these two ideas can form into one, providing moral boundaries of what is just in war and what is evil. In the context of human society, war often feels inevitable, especially when we consider the complexity of global politics and how intertwined various systems are. However, given how much connection humans have built over diplomatic systems and political stand points, strong diplomatic structures exist for the very problems that war brings on all sides of the party: hatred. However, what would war look like on a common moral ground if diplomacy fell short? In some cases, war is justifiable. For example, the act of self defense. This mechanism can be viewed as an action of protecting its people from an evil source. If there are no wars, there would only be one power taking advantage of the lack of self defense. When a nation wages war, it gives reasons for societal tensions and moral dilemma. There is never a legal obligation to oblige a country during war, but many experience forced obligation to serve their country. In many cases, people who did not explicitly fight for war still contributed to the war efforts through less heinous acts. Refusing to fight, even if the effort is negative or positive, takes a lot of courage to do, because it preserves the idea that one might have of their nation being inherently peaceful, and therefore, their act could be seen as patriotic. Those who do refuse war have a high sense of self or rationalized mindset. Within society, people who have refused to fight wars are spoken very ill of, causing negative connotation to their actions. Jeff McMahan’s views on Just War Theory are very innovative, and there are some things in his argument that are agreeable to an extent. The continuity of people going beyond their moral compass for the sake of following orders is very great, and is a common example of human nature, especially in war. The Milgram Experiment speaks many volumes within this realm of psychological theories. The emphasis McMahan makes on keeping people in check is very valid, and criticizes the human nature of fear, opening the perspective of this in a higher moral sense. However, it is still important to be on the optimistic side of this continuity, as society is always evolving with the hopes of living better lives. Many soldiers have a high sense of morality, and some are currently helping reform the war justice systems and war models. In conclusion, although war can be invasive, it is still necessary to have them because of the very complicated systems we live in today.
Boston, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
Reflections on Just War Theory
War is not always wrong, as the formation of organized violence can be justified in self-defense. If a state is attacking and posing a threat to your own state, you must defend it for the sake of your state’s survival and proliferation. It may be necessary to use methods that may end the lives of the attackers, however, as a soldier you have given up your protection. You transition from a protected citizen, where you aren’t classified as a target, therefore your death cannot be justified, to a combatant, who participates in the threat and possible destruction of another state. In accordance with The Principles of Jus in Bello, when you are considered a combatant or a soldier in war, you are putting your life and the lives of those you face at risk, therefore you renounce your immunity and innocence from the war. This distinction is important in terms of the principle of discrimination. This covers who are legitimate targets in war to prevent indiscriminate attacks against innocents who may be deemed as not being a part of the war. If a soldier is drafted into an unjust war, they are still capable of upholding honorable war methods. This would include following the principle of discrimination as stated previously, making sure only legitimate targets are being focused on. Nevertheless, the notion of an unjust war, or legitimate targets, entirely depends on the views of the nations at war. Many can twist these principles to make their reason to war just. Throughout history, many war acts were based on religion and other subjective topics which are different between cultures. The principles of war make it so that these subjectivities are conquered, and the world can hold the same/similar morals on how war is fought. However this has not provided a solution. Technically, with the right reasoning and manipulation of such principles, any war can be justified. With the principle of proportionality, however, you can gauge certain war acts as being justifiable or not. From The Principles of Jus In Bello, the principle of proportionality covers the amount of force is morally necessary. When classifying self-defense in war, you can determine whether the defense is excessive or not, based on the magnitude of the initial attack. Although the attack itself may have been from an unjust cause, the actions taken against it can be justified, insinuating that although the cause of war can be unjust, the way war is fought can be moral. One requires a combination of both the intrinsic and consequentialist model to classify war realistically. The intrinsicism model is necessary after determining the set proportionality of war acts. If, at the start of the war, the border is challenged, it would not be proportionate for the opposite nation to bomb the threatening nation’s hospitals. That would be immoral in accordance with the principles. However, if the attacking nation had begun with the bombing of the hospitals, an attack in retaliation that reflects the initial attack would still be immoral. The consequentialist model deems that war acts are only permissible if the outcome is just. If bombing the attacking nation’s hospitals in response to them bombing hospitals first brings an end to the war, that action would be justified. This, however, may become problematic as leaders may have different views of what is a proportionate attack or not. However, one cannot choose the intrinsicism model over the consequentialist model or vice versa. Both are needed to assess war acts.
Boston, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
War is always wrong. However, it may be justifiable. War being justified is not saying that it is a good thing to do, or that it is morally correct. These beliefs seem to fall between an intrinsic and consequential model because war is not right, but it may be considered justifiable. Neither intrinsicism nor consequentialism is realistic for a modern world, but properties of each may be applied to create a seemingly “just war theory”.Just War Theory bridges intrinsicism and consequentialism because it takes ideas from both and applies them to reality. The idea that actions of war are not okay is present in Just War Theory because society has come up with war crimes. It is not realistic to say that war will never occur though, and it is not more just or morally correct to push against war in certain situations. As described in In Between War and Peace, many opposed war, but also supported it when it was introduced as more than a theory: “...as a socialist, he was against war; and yet he enlisted in the army as soon as he crossed the border into Germany”. War, theoretically, never proves to be the same as war in reality. This idea also pushes away consequentialism because although war may occur, and acting in a certain way may provide a morally positive outcome, the acts committed do not become morally correct.
If a nation wages war for something that is immoral or unjust, then people should be able to refuse participation and protest it. This also supports the idea that if a nation is acting unjustly, then a group of people, which could be described as a rebel group, should be able to declare war against the corrupt government. However, this goes against Just War Theory because this definition is moral in theory, but when it may be applied is an entirely different question. How to gauge whether a feeling raised by a group is enough precedent for war, is still being argued, and Just War Theory skims just over it. If groups were constantly overthrowing governments, it would be considered wrong, but if no one ever stood up for themself, that would also be considered wrong. Just War Theory doesn’t give an answer to what is “right” in these situations, which makes them harder to navigate, particularly in the ever-changing world that is affected by media. Is it really right or wrong to engage a group of people with common thoughts with the goal to create positive change, while understanding that the process may cause damage? This question brings up the idea of conspiracies, and their legal definitions. Cornell’s law website states that a “conspiracy is an agreement between two or more people to commit an illegal act,” which can be used to describe any rebel group that has led a revolution to found a new country. For example, the United States wouldn’t exist if no one had gone against the English Parliament and resisted oppressive rule. Now, this would be considered going against the idea of Just War Theory, even though it could be argued to be better for both parties involved.
Boston, Mass, US
Posts: 5
Just War Theory Reflection
War is a complicated topic, there are many ways to justify many points of view and that is why it has been up for discussion for so many years. People have different experiences, some personal and some from the outside, offering even more conflicting opinions. War is not always wrong and the use of large-scale organized violence can sometimes be justified. With this being said, there are certain restrictions these leaders have to abide by to make it justified. The times that war is the only option are not common yet they certainly exist. Much like the Just War Theory states, all exhausts have to be tried in order to resort back to war. What this means is that all attempts to keep peace and not kill have had to be thought through and put to the test before we can decide it is okay to start using violence as the answer. We can see this in Excerpt 1: Just War Theory-Jus In Bello (Encyclopedia of Philosophy), when they talk about the principles of Just War Theory, “The resulting damage that war wrecks tends to be very high for most economies and so theorists have advised that war should not be lightly accepted: once unleashed, war is not like a sport that can be quickly stopped” (page 3). This is something important to consider because nations can get ruined because of how much money and distraction is caused by war and inevitably never fully come back from it. Weapons and organizing armies costs millions but in order to win and save lives, they are needed when going against a powerful enemy. Due to its extremity, it needs to be fully confirmed that war is the only option left because it is declared. This decision of it being the last and final option should not come from that nation's ruler alone due to basis but rather an organization whose job is that. In the modern world, for the average citizen, it is easy for us to say we would follow the intrinsicism model. Yet most of us have never been leading a group of soldiers or been a soldier, where millions of peoples lives are in your hands, including your own and you have to make a decision on the spot. For example, if there was a shelter where they knew the enemy's citizens were staying to seek safety but there were hundreds of bombs being stored there by the enemy as well, is it wrong to bomb those to eliminate the deadly bombs that can be used against their own troops? That is something that needs to be considered before we state we follow one model or the other, what we would do if we were actually at war. This is why the conversation of war and justifying actions during war is such a hard one to grasp because there are so many ways to look at it. If your country declared war but you believed it was morally wrong, then it is brave to stick up and not fight because you believe this is wrong. This is what a nonconformist would do while the majority would go with the group, meaning they would ignore what they know and believe to be wrong in order to not stick out. When all others are following the authority, they are not, they are resisting, this is brave. This is why it is more cowardice to fight in a war you do not think is right. Also by fighting in a war, you are choosing to put your life on the lines for whatever you are fighting for, meaning you should wholeheartedly believe in the cause and actually want to fight the war. With this being said, not every citizen can go around following what they believe because then there may not be enough people to be in the army. Therefore, there needs to be some kind of boundary set that you have the right to follow your own beliefs but there have to be some kind of limits set. Overall, war being justified or not is such an expansive topic and can be taken in many different directions by people with different backgrounds regarding war.
Dorchester Center, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
Reflection on Just War Theory
In almost anyone’s mind, they would think of war as an inherently bad thing, which should be avoided at any cost, and although it is seen as a bad thing, when in accordance with the correct regulations and moral laws, it is not always wrong. If two countries agree to have exhausted all other forms of diplomacy or de-escalation, war may be necessary in order to reconcile them. On top of this, violence and aggression are inherent parts of human nature, therefore making war almost impossible to avoid in the grand scheme of the worldwide diplomatic system, when there is always one person or a group of people holding power over another. Although it would be in many countries’ best interests to follow the model of consequentialism, there are always points at which a country cannot go past unless exhausting other methods first. For example, a country would almost certainly be inclined to use a nuclear weapon if it meant the immediate end of a conflict, and therefore the saving of many of their own soldiers’ lives, even if the conflict was not deserving of such an attack. This sort of scenario is one of many which Just War Theory accounts for, creating a link between consequentialist and intrinsicist views by allowing an attack to be made, but limiting it to one proportionate to the goal of the conflict in the first place.
If a country goes to war for unjust reasons, it is ultimately up to the citizens themselves as to whether or not they choose to participate in the war effort, because the individual’s will is often something that can’t be forcibly changed by a government mandate. On the other hand, an individual’s will in this context can be more likely changed by a group that they share more affinity with, for example, in the reading: Between Peace and War, the German Social Democratic party, which was often against war, changed their stance to support it when World War One started. “Now thousands of Germans gathered in the streets not to protest the war but to show their support for it (....) As a Jew, Toller had experienced discrimination; as a socialist, he was against war; and yet he enlisted in the army as soon as he crossed the border into Germany.” This ties not only to the question of whether or not citizens should participate in an unjust war, but also the question of whether it is better to fight in an unjust war alongside one’s countrymen, or refuse to fight in an unjust war for their country. As I stated before, each person acts according to their own will and moral compass, but then again, their moral compass can be swayed by a variety of factors, as shown by the quote In short, the individual’s own ethical guidelines for themselves are purely a product of their environment. In my own opinion, it is the better option to stick by your own moral compass, even if it means betraying a group (and in this context, a country) you previously thought so highly of.
Boston, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
Reflections on Just War Theory
I do not think that war is always wrong, however actions during and after a war can change the justifications. Following the model of the just war theory, killing is wrong, but who is being killed can shift views. If a nation is attacked first with no warning, they have a right to defend themselves on the basis that they are defending their citizens. I think an even more specific form of having the right to go to war on the idea of protecting citizens is if soldiers who are the aggressors enlisted with their free will. Even if they thought they were fighting for a just cause, they still attacked another country without substantial time spent finding a peaceful solution. For example, young soldiers who joined the Nazi’s because of a twisted form of hyper-nationalism that led them to execute Jewish people.
Certain aspects of war can be broken down into two categories, the intrinsicism model, that certain actions in war are either 100% bad or 100% good, and the consequentialism model, that there are justifications for bad actions if the outcome is beneficial. In modern times I think the consequentialism model is the most repetitive excuse for countries to enact violence another. Many countries tend to follow the model of “act first, think later” because they feel the need to catch another country off guard, in order to boost their means of a just war. That means, entering a war knowing that winning is guaranteed. When following consequentialist thinking, the scale of violence used is usually disproportionate and may make a war unjust. As stated in Excerpt 2, “the principle of proportionality concerns how much force is morally appropriate.” Using a modern example, Russia is substantially bigger than Ukraine, to the point where Ukraine fights back against Russian forces with a vast majority of foreign aid. This inequality in power may give Russia the idea that their war is just, but for the Ukrainians their war is just for another reason, defense.
Any nation that wages an unjust war has a vast majority of citizens that do not fight. Whether pacifists or eligible to enlist, those people have a choice to make, support their country, even if they do not believe in their cause, or face discrimination. I think that citizens should have the ability to refuse to participate in an unjust war, because their country isn't what defines them. While nationalism and togetherness are promoted in war countries, it is the individuals who participate who give their lives and resources for the cause. To make citizens participate in something against their belief is the government becoming too involved in the lives of citizens. However, if each citizen acts on their own accord, sub groups may form that will cause even more violence in that country, only this time internally. Widespread chaos, and fights on domestic soil lead to the destruction of not just the country, but the people who may not even have taken the lives of others.
Boston, Massachusetts , US
Posts: 5
Reflections on Just War Theory
I believe that war isn’t always war and sometimes the violence can be justified. Although this is a controversial statement, I believe that the Just War Theory allows for an understanding of war. It helps with acknowledging the moral weight of violence and seeing that in extreme cases violence may be necessary to achieve what is needed to move on. The Just War Theory helps us understand the consideration of the potential outcomes and the balance of peace and pragmatic realities of conflicts. I believe that the Just War Theory can be a bridge between the two ideas because it helps to balance morality against violence with the potential for just outcomes. If the reasons for war are legitimized with reasons like self defense or protecting your people, then it can be possible that a war is justified since there is a good possible outcome as well (peace and justice). If a nation is waging for unjust reasons with unjust outcomes, I believe that citizens should refuse to participate in the war. As we saw in one of the articles that we read for homework, the German people were going against the war and refusing to participate, but once the war was in motion all the protest suddenly came to a halt. It was either radio silence or people cheering for the other side. This happens because people do not want to be singled out and feel as though they are betraying their country. I feel as though not fighting in defense of your nation or fighting in a war that you believe is morally wrong can be a mix of both. I think that people who choose not to fight in the war because of their morals can be completely correct and that is their own personal preference, but at the same time while they aren’t fighting somebody else is fighting and feels morally wrong doing so. Same goes for the other way around with the fighting but knowing it’s morally wrong. If you don’t do so, somebody else will. I believe that it is 50/50. I both agree and disagree with McMahan’s statement. He explains that the battlefield doesn’t “absolve” a soldier's moral responsibility and if they are fighting for an unjust cause. He explains that if the war is unjust then actions may be taken and be morally compromised with or without the soldier’s conduct. The rules of Jus In Bello help explain that proportionality is ensuring that the harm caused by military actions will be proportional to the military advantage gained. This can be applied to McMahan’s argument and help open eyes. Since the soldiers are the ones navigating the people through the war, they provide a basis for conducting themselves with honor. Although, I disagree since the principles of Jus In Bello is that such discrimination and proportionality helps soldiers to adhere to the ethical standard with a flawed context. Soldiers tend to find themselves in situations where they have to limit the agency over the war’s justification.
Boston, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
Reflections on Just War Theory
War can only be moral if it is fair for all sides, so war is moral if its cause, conduct, and resolutions are justifiable. War is unethical if the circumstances surrounding it are unethical. Thus, the consequentialist model is more suited for the contemporary world. If war itself is not morally wrong, then the cause of the war or the conduct in warfare is often morally wrong. If violence and conflict are human nature, then so are making decisions and believing in morals and ethics. Just War Theory lays down the rules that a nation’s leaders and fighters have to follow, so they are morally obligated to follow them. Just War Theory was created to prevent unnecessary death or violence and to make war and warfare fair because of the idea that everyone should be respected even in war. If a person breaches any of the rules, they must be held accountable because they neglect the responsibility of respecting the enemy. Therefore, people have the obligation to act morally in war.
As the Just War Theory is the framework of how war should be conducted, it does not resolve that war itself is immoral. Just War Theory supports the consequentialist instead of the intrinsicist model because it shares more beliefs with the consequentialist model. For example, if two countries claim a piece of land as theirs and the other side has no right to own it, they may fail to resolve the situation through negotiation or by agreeing to the land’s history or culture. In the consequentialist model, both sides have the ethical right to wage a war against each other, provided that neither side breaches the rules of Just War Theory. In the intrinsic model, both sides will likely never reach a conclusion through diplomacy due to the intense conflicts in their beliefs. Even if they agree on morals, they may not agree on a compromise. As a result, war should instead be the final compromise to a problem, one which is just if it is the only solution to such a problem. In this way, Just War Theory follows the consequentialist model because war is only moral if the circumstances surrounding it are just.
Additionally, if a nation wages war upon an unjust or immoral cause, its citizens should be able to refuse to participate in the war. Philosopher Bertrand Russell says that people have the right to be conscientious objectors when they believe their nation fails to treat an enemy like its own citizens or believe that violence is against their morals because they feel empathy for their soldiers and the enemy. Just as how people are obligated to act morally in war, people who are opposed to war are morally obligated to not participate in war. If a soldier tortures a prisoner, they neglect to treat the prisoner fairly. If a conscientious objector decides to participate in war, they may feel that they are neglecting their morals. Just War Theory thus affects those who participate in war and those who oppose it.
Boston, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 4
Reflection on Just War Theory
The question of whether citizens should refuse to participate in a war they believe is unjust is based on ideas such as one's ethical beliefs, loyalty to their country, and individual responsibility. This problem makes us think about what it means to be courageous in the context of war and whether it is more courageous to go against an unjust idea/conflict or cowardly to fight in a war one believes is wrong.
Generally, wars can be seen as unjust for many reasons, such as not having a legit cause for defense, the violation of human rights, or being motivated by greed/power. When a nation enters a war like this, citizens may find it hard to pick a side. Should they stray away from their ways and disobey their government, or fight for something that they themselves do not believe in.
Refusing to fight in a war one sees as unjust can take a lot of courage. It often means facing criticism, legal consequences, or even violence. For example, in the Vietnam War, Many people who resisted being drafted faced imprisonment and social exclusion. Their choice to refuse military service was based on the belief that some wars are fundamentally wrong. In this way, it’s fair to argue that it takes more bravery to go against what the government says than to follow orders without question.
On the other hand, some people might argue that fighting in a war one believes is morally wrong makes them a coward. This viewpoint suggests that those who blindly follow orders lose their own beliefs. By not questioning the severity of their actions, they risk having the responsibility of these actions being put on them. Soldiers have a duty to think deeply about the conflicts they are involved in, and failing to do so can lead to immense damage and tragedy.
The outcomes of these actions can vary depending on the political views and unity of a nation. In a democracy, a refusal to fight may lead to discussions about the war’s justification, potentially causing it to end. In contrast, in more authoritarian regimes, disagreement could result in harsh punishments, escalating the conflict and leading to suffering for many. One example of this is The Christmas Truce of 1914. Many nations were in heated altercations throughout World War 1. When Christmas approached, many of the armies, such as the British, German, and French created a ceasefire along the western front. Soldiers exchanged gifts, ideas, and even sang Christmas carols. This adds to the idea that many people are fighting for their government, and not their beliefs. These soldiers have a lot in common, and war puts a pin in those relationships and focuses on what the higher people believe.
In the excerpt about Just War Theory, it talks about what circumstances play into the decision for starting the war. It states that in order to start a war, the two sides must agree on what extremes the war will go to. There are some instances where the two sides differ and cannot decide on a limit. This causes both sides to be able to escalate a war against a group that they already do not like or see as “not human”. This creates a problem that can lead to many people getting hurt for reasons that could have been avoided.
In conclusion, while it’s crucial for people to think about their moral responsibilities during war, the problem is in balancing personal beliefs with duties to one’s country and society. It raises important questions about justice, loyalty, and courage. While personal belief is important, the possible trouble that comes with people disagreeing must be taken into account, as it could lead to both good changes and destructive outcomes.
Hyde Park, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
Just War Theory and World War 1
I think war can be justified. I think there are two sides of whether war can be seen as a right and it ranges from internal and external beliefs. Internally, war is justified if most citizens are ready to die for the cause. It must be and educated decision and for the betterment of their country and the world around them. Externally war can be justified if they abide by the rules of war: using a necessary amount of force, it is a last resort, they have good intentions, and there is a just cause.
I think the consequentialism model is more accurate for the modern world because it's more realistic. People are killed every single day and killing even though it's bad has been normalized in many countries through the use of tv shows and local news. Also there is a decrease in the belief in religion which usually states that killings are morally incorrect. Therefore with the normalization and lack of moral boundary, a more consequentialist model would be in line with human morals today.
I think citizens should refuse to participate in the war effort because killing someone is not a joke or in any way permissible. There must be a good reason for an individual to kill another, so if citizens do not support their nation's war effort then they shouldn’t have to fight. However, if the war is starting to kill and harm too many people from your nation then you will have to fight back. At that point, it is either killed or be killed, and you must kill for means of survival.
I do think it takes a lot of courage to not fight in defense of your nation in a war in which you believe is morally wrong. There is a lot of societal pressure these days to conform to the war efforts of your country and its human nature to do that. I do believe it's cowardice to fight in a war you don’t believe in, but I do understand why a person might do that. As I said previously, there is a lot of societal pressure from friends and family, but it could also be the law in your country that you must fight in the war. This is similar to the American draft system. It may also be the only way for a person to get the money to provide for their family. Either way, every circumstance is different, so we shouldn’t become prone to fundamental attribution error and assume that a person is cowardice since they fought in a war they don’t believe in.
I think one of the consequences of people acting on their own accord is the third principle “the principle of responsibility, which demands an examination of where responsibility lies in war” (Excerpt 3). I think responsibility lies not only in if you choose to fight but if you don’t choose to fight. These consequences range from guilt to war crimes. There must be an abundance of thought that comes from even thinking about wars as an option. There will be consequences for people within and outside of the war, so it is advised to proceed with caution.
Dorchester Center, Massachusetts, US
Posts: 5
Is War Justifiable?
While I believe that war cannot be justified, in most cases, it is difficult to avoid or step away from due to history’s tendency of violent reliance, and the overexertion of global powers. Despite war ending tragically throughout history, in reference to the modern world, I believe that the consequentialist model is more realistic; it can definitely be argued that war is dangerous and leads to mass destruction but the consequentialist model offers insight of the possible victories and positive outcomes that emerge from violence. One of the most relevant examples is the defeat of Nazi Germany in World War II; the conflict was certainly brutal and horrific but it eventually led to the liberation of millions of Jews. The principles of jus ad bellum help to form a bridge or “middle-ground” between the intrinsicism and consequentialist models by aligning with the moral reasoning incorporated into intrinsicism and the outcomes described by consequentialism. However, it is difficult to state whether or not war is truly justifiable because just wars could be fought using unjust means and unjust wars could be fought through just means; the line between just and unjust is very blurry and definitions can be altered in order to fit the victor’s benefit.
When nations wage wars for unjust reasons, the question of whether or not weighs on the citizens, who are forced between choosing what is right for their morals or what is right for their nation. Volunteering to put your life on the line for your nation is one the most courageous things a person can do, but it can be argued that going against your nation for waging an unjust war is also extremely courageous. In the article “Between Peace and War,” Philosopher Bertran Russel states that: “The greatest difficulty was the purely psychological one of resisting mass suggestion, of which the force becomes terrific when the whole nation is in a state of collective excitement.” This quote, in reference to Russel’s position as a conscientious objector, who went against war as a whole, exemplifies the levels of courage that somebody must acquire in order to stand against their nation. Emphasized by the Obedience Theory, and the concepts behind “mob mentality,” it is incredibly difficult to stand against the majority out of fear of rejection, othering, or physical harm. These conscientious objectors, and others who stand against or refuse the war effort exemplify rare acts of defiance that ultimately puts their life in danger. While they are not volunteering outright to give up their lives, they still must face the consequences of their defiance, including exclusion, humiliation, banishment, execution, and imprisonment. However, the position of these conscientious objectors and the consequences they face brings up the dangers of allowing each and every individual to follow their own moral compass during wartime.While I do not believe that measures as extreme as a draft are necessary, I believe in the important of having a stable leadership figure(s) that takes control of panic-inducing situations in order to ensure the safety of the nation as a whole; if citizens were to act on their own moral compass, many would act irrationally as fear discards all rational thought.
The question of whether or not war is justifiable is much deeper than a simple yes or no; it is important to study the different models that observe wartime behaviors, and our past historical mistakes in order to determine the most rational solution to global issues.